Formally, a cardinal κ is defined to be weakly compact if it is uncountable and for every function f: [κ] 2 → {0, 1} there is a set of cardinality κ that is homogeneous for f. In this context, [κ] 2 means the set of 2-element subsets of κ, and a subset S of κ is homogeneous for fif and only if either all of [S]2 maps to 0 or all of it maps to 1.
The name "weakly compact" refers to the fact that if a cardinal is weakly compact then a certain related infinitary language satisfies a version of the compactness theorem; see below.
Equivalent formulations
The following are equivalent for any uncountable cardinal κ:
κ is weakly compact.
for every λ<κ, natural number n ≥ 2, and function f: [κ]n → λ, there is a set of cardinality κ that is homogeneous for f. (Drake 1974, chapter 7 theorem 3.5)
κ is inaccessible and has the tree property, that is, every tree of height κ has either a level of size κ or a branch of size κ.
Every linear order of cardinality κ has an ascending or a descending sequence of order type κ. (W. W. Comfort, S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ultrafilters, p.185)
κ has the extension property. In other words, for all U ⊂ Vκ there exists a transitive set X with κ ∈ X, and a subset S ⊂ X, such that (Vκ, ∈, U) is an elementary substructure of (X, ∈, S). Here, U and S are regarded as unary predicates.
For every set S of cardinality κ of subsets of κ, there is a non-trivial κ-complete filter that decides S.
κ is inaccessible and the infinitary languageLκ,κ satisfies the weak compactness theorem.
κ is inaccessible and the infinitary languageLκ,ω satisfies the weak compactness theorem.
κ is inaccessible and for every transitive set of cardinality κ with κ , , and satisfying a sufficiently large fragment of ZFC, there is an elementary embedding from to a transitive set of cardinality κ such that , with critical pointκ. (Hauser 1991, Theorem 1.3)
( defined as ) and every -complete filter of a -complete field of sets of cardinality is contained in a -complete ultrafilter. (W. W. Comfort, S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ultrafilters, p.185)
has Alexander's property, i.e. for any space with a -subbase with cardinality , and every cover of by elements of has a subcover of cardinality , then is -compact. (W. W. Comfort, S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ultrafilters, p.182--185)
is -compact. (W. W. Comfort, S. Negrepontis, The Theory of Ultrafilters, p.185)
A language Lκ,κ is said to satisfy the weak compactness theorem if whenever Σ is a set of sentences of cardinality at most κ and every subset with less than κ elements has a model, then Σ has a model. Strongly compact cardinals are defined in a similar way without the restriction on the cardinality of the set of sentences.
Properties
Every weakly compact cardinal is a reflecting cardinal, and is also a limit of reflecting cardinals. This means also that weakly compact cardinals are Mahlo cardinals, and the set of Mahlo cardinals less than a given weakly compact cardinal is stationary.
If is weakly compact, then there are chains of well-founded elementary end-extensions of of arbitrary length .[1]p.6
Weakly compact cardinals remain weakly compact in .[2] Assuming V = L, a cardinal is weakly compact iff it is 2-stationary.[3]
Drake, F. R. (1974), Set Theory: An Introduction to Large Cardinals, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 76, Elsevier Science Ltd, ISBN0-444-10535-2
Hauser, Kai (1991), "Indescribable Cardinals and Elementary Embeddings", Journal of Symbolic Logic, 56 (2), Association for Symbolic Logic: 439–457, doi:10.2307/2274692, JSTOR2274692, S2CID288779